1 (**************************************************************************)
4 (* ||A|| A project by Andrea Asperti *)
6 (* ||I|| Developers: *)
7 (* ||T|| The HELM team. *)
8 (* ||A|| http://helm.cs.unibo.it *)
10 (* \ / This file is distributed under the terms of the *)
11 (* v GNU General Public License Version 2 *)
13 (**************************************************************************)
15 include "basics/types.ma".
17 (* Most of the types we have seen so far are enumerated types, composed by a
18 finite set of alternatives, and records, composed by tuples of heteregoneous
19 elements. A more interesting case of type definition is when some of the rules
20 defining its elements are recursive, i.e. they allow the formation of more
21 elements of the type in terms of the already defined ones. The most typical case
22 is provided by the natural numbers, that can be defined as the smallest set
23 generated by a constant 0 and a successor function from natural numbers to natural
26 inductive nat : Type[0] ≝
30 (* The two terms O and S are called constructors: they define the signature of the
31 type, whose objects are the elements freely generated by means of them. So,
32 examples of natural numbers are O, S O, S (S O), S (S (S O)) and so on.
34 The language of Matita allows the definition of well founded recursive functions
35 over inductive types; in order to guarantee termination of recursion you are only
36 allowed to make recursive calls on structurally smaller arguments than the ones
37 you received in input. Most mathematical functions can be naturally defined in this
38 way. For instance, the sum of two natural numbers can be defined as follows *)
49 It is worth to observe that the previous algorithm works by recursion over the
50 first argument. This means that, for instance, (add O x) will reduce to x, as
51 expected, but (add x O) is stuck.
52 How can we prove that, for a generic x, (add x O) = x? The mathematical tool to do
53 it is called induction. The induction principle states that, given a property P(n)
54 over natural numbers, if we prove P(0) and prove that, for any m, P(m) implies P(S m),
55 than we can conclude P(n) for any n.
57 The elim tactic, allow you to apply induction in a very simple way. If your goal is
58 P(n), the invocation of
60 will break down your task to prove the two subgoals P(0) and ∀m.P(m) → P(S m).
62 Let us apply it to our case *)
64 lemma add_0: ∀a. add a O = a.
67 (* If you stop the computation here, you will see on the right the two subgoals
69 - ∀x. add x 0 = x → add (S x) O = S x
70 After normalization, both goals are trivial.
75 (* In a similar way, it is convenient to state a lemma about the behaviour of
76 add when the second argument is not zero. *)
78 lemma add_S : ∀a,b. add a (S b) = S (add a b).
80 (* In the same way as before, we proceed by induction over a. *)
82 #a #b elim a normalize //
85 (* We are now in the position to prove the commutativity of the sum *)
87 theorem add_comm : ∀a,b. add a b = add b a.
91 (* We have two sub goals:
93 G2: ∀x.(∀b. add x b = add b x) → ∀b. S (add x b) = add b (S x).
94 G1 is just our lemma add_O. For G2, we start introducing x and the induction
95 hypothesis IH; then, the goal is proved by rewriting using add_S and IH.
96 For Matita, the task is trivial and we can simply close the goal with // *)
102 inductive bool : Type[0] ≝
106 definition nat_of_bool ≝ λb. match b with
111 (* coercion nat_of_bool. ?? *)
113 (* Let us now define the following function: *)
115 definition twice ≝ λn.add n n.
120 We are interested to prove that for any natural number n there exists a natural
121 number m that is the integer half of n. This will give us the opportunity to
122 introduce new connectives and quantifiers and, later on, to make some interesting
123 consideration on proofs and computations. *)
125 theorem ex_half: ∀n.∃m. n = twice m ∨ n = S (twice m).
128 (* We proceed by induction on n, that breaks down to the following goals:
129 G1: ∃m.O = add O O ∨ O = S (add m m)
130 G2: ∀x.(∃m. x = add m m ∨ x = S (add m m))→ ∃m. S x = add m m ∨ S x = S (add m m)
131 The only way we have to prove an existential goal is by exhibiting the witness,
132 that in the case of first goal is O. We do it by apply the term called ex_intro
133 instantiated by the witness. Then, it is clear that we must follow the left branch
134 of the disjunction. One way to do it is by applying the term or_introl, that is
135 the first constructor of the disjunction. However, remembering the names of
136 constructors can be annyoing: we can invoke the application of the n-th
137 constructor of an inductive type (inferred by the current goal) by typing %n. At
138 this point we are left with the subgoal O = add O O, that is closed by
139 computation. It is worth to observe that invoking automation at depth /3/ would
140 also automatically close G1.
143 [@(ex_intro … O) %1 //
148 The case of G2 is more complex. We should start introducing x and the
150 IH: ∃m. x = add m m ∨ x = S (add m m)
151 At this point we should assume the existence of m enjoying the inductive
152 hypothesis. To eliminate the existential from the context we can just use the
153 case tactic. This situation where we introduce something into the context and
154 immediately eliminate it by case analysis is so frequent that Matita provides a
155 convenient shorthand: you can just type a single "*".
156 The star symbol should be reminiscent of an explosion: the idea is that you have
157 a structured hypothesis, and you ask to explode it into its constituents. In the
158 case of the existential, it allows to pass from a goal of the shape
160 to a goal of the shape
164 (* At this point we are left with a new goal with the following shape
165 G3: ∀m. x = add m m ∨ x = S (add m m) → ....
166 We should introduce m, the hypothesis H: x = add m m ∨ x = S (add m m), and
167 then reason by cases on this hypothesis. It is the same situation as before:
168 we explode the disjunctive hypothesis into its possible consituents. In the case
169 of a disjunction, the * tactic allows to pass from a goal of the form
171 to two subgoals of the form
175 (* In the first subgoal, we are under the assumption that x = add m m. The half
176 of (S x) is hence m, and we have to prove the right branch of the disjunction.
177 In the second subgoal, we are under the assumption that x = S (add m m). The halh
178 of (S x) is hence (S m), and have to follow the left branch of the disjunction.
180 [@(ex_intro … m) /2/ | @(ex_intro … (S m)) normalize /2/
185 Computing vs. Proving
187 Instead of proving the existence of a number corresponding to the half of n,
188 we could be interested in computing it. The best way to do it is to define this
189 division operation together with the remainder, that in our case is just a
190 boolean value: tt if the input term is even, and ff if the input term is odd.
191 Since we must return a pair, we could use a suitably defined record type, or
192 simply a product type nat × bool, defined in the basic library. The product type
193 is just a sort of general purpose record, with standard fields fst and snd, called
195 A pair of values n and m is written (pair … m n) or \langle n,m \rangle - visually
198 We first write down the function, and then discuss it.*)
204 let 〈q,r〉 ≝ (div2 a) in
211 (* The function is computed by recursion over the input n. If n is 0, then the
212 quotient is 0 and the remainder is tt. If n = S a, we start computing the half
213 of a, say 〈q,b〉. Then we have two cases according to the possible values of b:
214 if b is tt, then we must return 〈q,ff〉, while if b = ff then we must return
217 It is important to point out the deep, substantial analogy between the algorithm
218 for computing div2 and the the proof of ex_half. In particular ex_half returns a
219 proof of the kind ∃n.A(n)∨B(n): the really informative content in it is the
220 witness n and a boolean indicating which one between the two conditions A(n) and
221 B(n) is met. This is precisely the quotient-remainder pair returned by div2.
222 In both cases we proceed by recurrence (respectively, induction or recursion) over
223 the input argument n. In case n = 0, we conclude the proof in ex_half by providing
224 the witness O and a proof of A(O); this corresponds to returning the pair 〈O,ff〉 in
225 div2. Similarly, in the inductive case n = S a, we must exploit the inductive
226 hypothesis for a (i.e. the result of the recursive call), distinguishing two subcases
227 according to the the two possibilites A(a) or B(a) (i.e. the two possibile values of
228 the remainder for a). The reader is strongly invited to check all remaining details.
230 Let us now prove that our div2 function has the expected behaviour.
233 lemma div2SO: ∀n,q. div2 n = 〈q,ff〉 → div2 (S n) = 〈q,tt〉.
234 #n #q #H normalize >H normalize // qed.
236 lemma div2S1: ∀n,q. div2 n = 〈q,tt〉 → div2 (S n) = 〈S q,ff〉.
237 #n #q #H normalize >H normalize // qed.
239 lemma div2_ok: ∀n,q,r. div2 n = 〈q,r〉 → n = add (nat_of_bool r) (twice q).
241 [#q #r #H normalize in H; destruct //
243 cut (div2 a = 〈fst … (div2 a), snd … (div2 a)〉) [//]
244 cases (snd … (div2 a))
245 [#H >(div2S1 … H) #H1 destruct normalize @eq_f >add_S @(Hind … H)
246 |#H >(div2SO … H) #H1 destruct normalize @eq_f @(Hind … H)
251 Mixing proofs and computations
253 There is still another possibility, however, namely to mix the program and its
254 specification into a single entity. The idea is to refine the output type of the
255 div2 function: it should not be just a generic pair 〈q,r〉 of natural numbers but a
256 specific pair satisfying the specification of the function. In other words, we need
257 the possibility to define, for a type A and a property P over A, the subset type
258 {a:A|P(a)} of all elements a of type A that satisfy the property P. Subset types
259 are just a particular case of the so called dependent types, that is types that
260 can depend over arguments (such as arrays of a specified length, taken as a
261 parameter).These kind of types are quite unusual in traditional programming
262 languages, and their study is one of the new frontiers of the current research on
265 There is nothing special in a subset type {a:A|P(a)}: it is just a record composed
266 by an element of a of type A and a proof of P(a). The crucial point is to have a
267 language reach enough to comprise proofs among its expressions.
270 record Sub (A:Type[0]) (P:A → Prop) : Type[0] ≝
274 definition qr_spec ≝ λn.λp.∀q,r. p = 〈q,r〉 → n = add (nat_of_bool r) (twice q).
276 (* We can now construct a function from n to {p|qr_spec n p} by composing the objects
279 definition div2P: ∀n. Sub (nat×bool) (qr_spec n) ≝ λn.
280 mk_Sub ?? (div2 n) (div2_ok n).
282 (* But we can also try do directly build such an object *)
284 definition div2Pagain : ∀n.Sub (nat×bool) (qr_spec n).
286 [@(mk_Sub … 〈O,ff〉) normalize #q #r #H destruct //
288 cut (p = 〈fst … p, snd … p〉) [//]
290 [#H @(mk_Sub … 〈S (fst … p),ff〉) #q #r #H1 destruct @eq_f >add_S @(qrspec … H)
291 |#H @(mk_Sub … 〈fst … p,tt〉) #q #r #H1 destruct @eq_f @(qrspec … H)
295 example full7: (div2Pagain (S(S(S(S(S(S(S O)))))))) = ?.
299 example quotient7: witness … (div2Pagain (S(S(S(S(S(S(S O)))))))) = ?.
302 example quotient8: witness … (div2Pagain (twice (twice (twice (twice (S O))))))
303 = 〈twice (twice (twice (S O))), ff〉.