X-Git-Url: http://matita.cs.unibo.it/gitweb/?a=blobdiff_plain;f=helm%2Fsoftware%2Fmatita%2Fnlibrary%2Ftopology%2Figft.ma;h=66c7dd3a14e9dd9811d43847bb3aef37d7c0d829;hb=8d321a03cf328b85fe7c084bb22685673633d2ee;hp=3c97b9c25000735971c09018c1a1f4c42a6e86a3;hpb=a8aaa095aad443c8eca8f64e3f22f54615e8dd9b;p=helm.git diff --git a/helm/software/matita/nlibrary/topology/igft.ma b/helm/software/matita/nlibrary/topology/igft.ma index 3c97b9c25..66c7dd3a1 100644 --- a/helm/software/matita/nlibrary/topology/igft.ma +++ b/helm/software/matita/nlibrary/topology/igft.ma @@ -12,12 +12,20 @@ the formalization of the paper by S.Berardi and S. Valentini. The tutorial is by Enrico Tassi. +The tutorial spends a considerable amount of effort in defining +notations that resemble the ones used in the original paper. We believe +this a important part of every formalization, not only for the estetic +point of view, but also from the practical point of view. Being +consistent allows to follow the paper in a pedantic way, and hopefully +to make the formalization (at least the definitions and proved +statements) readable to the author of the paper. + Orientering ----------- TODO -buttons, PG-interaction-model, sequent window, script window +buttons, PG-interaction-model, sequent window, script window, ncheck The library, inclusion of `sets/sets.ma`, notation defined: Ω^A. Symbols (see menu: View ▹ TeX/UTF-8 Table): @@ -40,6 +48,7 @@ some notation attached to them: - A ∪ B `A \cup B` - A ∩ B `A \cap B` +- A ≬ B `A \between B` - x ∈ A `x \in A` - Ω^A, that is the type of the subsets of A, `\Omega ^ A` @@ -219,38 +228,186 @@ as subscript), separating them with a comma followed by a little space. The first (technical) definition -------------------------------- +Before defining the cover relation as an inductive predicate, one +has to notice that the infinity rule uses, in its hypotheses, the +cover relation between two subsets, while the inductive predicate +we are going to define relates an element and a subset. + +An option would be to unfold the definition of cover between subsets, +but we prefer to define the abstract notion of cover between subsets +(so that we can attach a (ambiguous) notation to it). + +Anyway, to ease the understaing of the definition of the cover relation +between subsets, we first define the inductive predicate unfolding the +definition, and we later refine it with. + +DOCEND*) + +ninductive xcover (A : Ax) (U : Ω^A) : A → CProp[0] ≝ +| xcreflexivity : ∀a:A. a ∈ U → xcover A U a +| xcinfinity : ∀a:A.∀i:𝐈 a. (∀y.y ∈ 𝐂 a i → xcover A U y) → xcover A U a. + +(*DOCBEGIN + +We defined the xcover (x will be removed in the final version of the +definition) as an inductive predicate. The arity of the inductive +predicate has to be carefully analyzed: + +> (A : Ax) (U : Ω^A) : A → CProp[0] + +The syntax separates with `:` abstractions that are fixed for every +constructor (introduction rule) and abstractions that can change. In that +case the parameter `U` is abstracted once and forall in front of every +constructor, and every occurrence of the inductive predicate is applied to +`U` in a consistent way. Arguments abstracted on the right of `:` are not +constant, for example the xcinfinity constructor introduces `a ◃ U`, +but under the assumption that (for every y) `y ◃ U`. In that rule, the left +had side of the predicate changes, thus it has to be abstrated (in the arity +of the inductive predicate) on the right of `:`. +DOCEND*) + +(* ncheck xcreflexivity. *) + +(*DOCBEGIN + +We want now to abstract out `(∀y.y ∈ 𝐂 a i → xcover A U y)` and define +a notion `cover_set` to which a notation `𝐂 a i ◃ U` can be attached. + +This notion has to be abstracted over the cover relation (whose +type is the arity of the inductive `xcover` predicate just defined). + +Then it has to be abstracted over the arguments of that cover relation, +i.e. the axiom set and the set U, and the subset (in that case `𝐂 a i`) +sitting on the left hand side of `◃`. DOCEND*) ndefinition cover_set : - ∀c: ∀A:Ax.Ω^A → A → CProp[0]. ∀A:Ax.∀C,U:Ω^A. CProp[0] + ∀cover: ∀A:Ax.Ω^A → A → CProp[0]. ∀A:Ax.∀C,U:Ω^A. CProp[0] ≝ - λc: ∀A:Ax.Ω^A → A → CProp[0]. λA,C,U.∀y.y ∈ C → c A U y. + λcover. λA, C,U. ∀y.y ∈ C → cover A U y. -ndefinition cover_set_interactive : - ∀c: ∀A:Ax.Ω^A → A → CProp[0]. ∀A:Ax.∀C,U:Ω^A. CProp[0]. -#cover; #A; #C; #U; napply (∀y:A.y ∈ C → ?); napply cover; -##[ napply A; -##| napply U; -##| napply y; -##] -nqed. +(*DOCBEGIN + +The `ndefinition` command takes a name, a type and body (of that type). +The type can be omitted, and in that case it is inferred by the system. +If the type is given, the system uses it to infer implicit arguments +of the body. In that case all types are left implicit in the body. + +We now define the notation `a ◃ b`. Here the keywork `hvbox` +and `break` tell the system how to wrap text when it does not +fit the screen (they can be safely ignore for the scope of +this tutorial). we also add an interpretation for that notation, +where the (abstracted) cover relation is implicit. The system +will not be able to infer it from the other arguments `C` and `U` +and will thus prompt the user for it. This is also why we named this +interpretation `covers set temp`: we will later define another +interpretation in which the cover relation is the one we are going to +define. + +DOCEND*) -(* a \ltri b *) notation "hvbox(a break ◃ b)" non associative with precedence 45 for @{ 'covers $a $b }. interpretation "covers set temp" 'covers C U = (cover_set ?? C U). +(*DOCBEGIN + +We can now define the cover relation using the `◃` notation for +the premise of infinity. + +DOCEND*) + ninductive cover (A : Ax) (U : Ω^A) : A → CProp[0] ≝ -| creflexivity : ∀a:A. a ∈ U → cover ? U a -| cinfinity : ∀a:A.∀i:𝐈 a. 𝐂 a i ◃ U → cover ? U a. +| creflexivity : ∀a. a ∈ U → cover ? U a +| cinfinity : ∀a. ∀i. 𝐂 a i ◃ U → cover ? U a. +(** screenshot "cover". *) napply cover; nqed. +(*DOCBEGIN + +Note that the system accepts the definition +but prompts the user for the relation the `cover_set` notion is +abstracted on. + +![The system asks for a cover relation][cover] + +The orizontal line separates the hypotheses from the conclusion. +The `napply cover` command tells the system that the relation +it is looking for is exactly our first context entry (i.e. the inductive +predicate we are defining, up to α-conversion); while the `nqed` command +ends a definition or proof. + +We can now define the interpretation for the cover relation between an +element and a subset fist, then between two subsets (but this time +we fixed the relation `cover_set` is abstracted on). + +DOCEND*) + interpretation "covers" 'covers a U = (cover ? U a). -(* interpretation "covers set" 'covers a U = (cover_set cover ? a U). *) +interpretation "covers set" 'covers a U = (cover_set cover ? a U). + +(*DOCBEGIN + +We will proceed similarly for the fish relation, but before going +on it is better to give a short introduction to the proof mode of Matita. +We define again the `cover_set` term, but this time we will build +its body interactively. In λ-calculus Matita is based on, CIC, proofs +and terms share the same syntax, and it thus possible to use the +commands devoted to build proof term to build regular definitions. + +DOCEND*) + + +ndefinition xcover_set : + ∀c: ∀A:Ax.Ω^A → A → CProp[0]. ∀A:Ax.∀C,U:Ω^A. CProp[0]. +(** screenshot "xcover-set-1". *) +(*DOCBEGIN +The system asks for a proof of the full statement, in an empty context. +![xcover_set proof step ][xcover-set-1] +The `#` command in the ∀-introduction rule, it gives a name to an +assumption putting it in the context, and generates a λ-abstraction +in the proof term. +DOCEND*) +#cover; #A; #C; #U; (** screenshot "xcover-set-2". *) +(*DOCBEGIN +![xcover_set proof step ][xcover-set-2] +We have now to provide a proposition, and we exhibit it. We left +a part of it implicit; since the system cannot infer it it will +ask it later. Note that the type of `∀y:A.y ∈ C → ?` is a proposition +whenever `?` is. +DOCEND*) +napply (∀y:A.y ∈ C → ?); (** screenshot "xcover-set-3". *) +(*DOCBEGIN +![xcover_set proof step ][xcover-set-3] +The proposition we want to provide is an application of the +cover relation we have abstracted in the context. The command +`napply`, if the given term has not the expected type (in that +case it is a product versus a proposition) it applies it to as many +implicit arguments as necessary (in that case `? ? ?`). +DOCEND*) +napply cover; (** screenshot "xcover-set-4". *) +(*DOCBEGIN +![xcover_set proof step ][xcover-set-4] +The system will now ask in turn the three implicit arguments +passed to cover. The syntax `##[` allows to start a branching +to tackle every sub proof individually, otherwise every command +is applied to every subrpoof. The command `##|` switches to the next +subproof and `##]` ends the branching. +DOCEND*) +##[ napply A; +##| napply U; +##| napply y; +##] +nqed. + +(*DOCBEGIN +The definition of fish works exactly the same way as for cover, except +that it is defined as a coinductive proposition. +DOCEND*) ndefinition fish_set ≝ λf:∀A:Ax.Ω^A → A → CProp[0]. λA,U,V. @@ -270,22 +427,96 @@ nqed. interpretation "fish set" 'fish A U = (fish_set fish ? U A). interpretation "fish" 'fish a U = (fish ? U a). +(*DOCBEGIN + +Matita is able to generate elimination rules for inductive types, +but not introduction rules for the coinductive case. + +DOCEND*) + +(* ncheck cover_rect_CProp0. *) + +(*DOCBEGIN + +We thus have to define the introduction rule for fish by corecursion. +Here we again use the proof mode of Matita to exhibit the body of the +corecursive function. + +DOCEND*) + nlet corec fish_rec (A:Ax) (U: Ω^A) (P: Ω^A) (H1: P ⊆ U) - (H2: ∀a:A. a ∈ P → ∀j: 𝐈 a. 𝐂 a j ≬ P): - ∀a:A. ∀p: a ∈ P. a ⋉ U ≝ ?. -#a; #p; napply cfish; (** screenshot "def-fish-rec". *) -##[ napply H1; napply p; -##| #i; ncases (H2 a p i); #x; *; #xC; #xP; @; ##[napply x] - @; ##[ napply xC ] napply (fish_rec ? U P); nassumption; + (H2: ∀a:A. a ∈ P → ∀j: 𝐈 a. 𝐂 a j ≬ P): ∀a:A. ∀p: a ∈ P. a ⋉ U ≝ ?. +(** screenshot "def-fish-rec-1". *) +(*DOCBEGIN +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-1] +Note the first item of the context, it is the corecursive function we are +defining. This item allows to perform the recursive call, but we will be +allowed to do such call only after having generated a constructor of +the fish coinductive type. + +We introduce `a` and `p`, and then return the fish constructor `cfish`. +Since the constructor accepts two arguments, the system asks for them. +DOCEND*) +#a; #p; napply cfish; (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-2". *) +(*DOCBEGIN +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-2] +The first one is a proof that `a ∈ U`. This can be proved using `H1` and `p`. +With the `nchange` tactic we change `H1` into an equivalent form (this step +can be skipped, since the systeem would be able to unfold the definition +of inclusion by itself) +DOCEND*) +##[ nchange in H1 with (∀b.b∈P → b∈U); + + (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-2-1". *) napply H1; + (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-3". *) nassumption; +(*DOCBEGIN +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-2-1] +It is now clear that `H1` can be applied. Again `napply` adds two +implicit arguments to `H1 ? ?`, obtaining a proof of `? ∈ U` given a proof +that `? ∈ P`. Thanks to unification, the system understands that `?` is actually +`a`, and it asks a proof that `a ∈ P`. +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-3] +The `nassumption` tactic looks for the required proof in the context, and in +that cases finds it in the last context position. + +We move now to the second branch of the proof, corresponding to the second +argument of the `cfish` constructor. +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-4] +DOCEND*) +##| (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-4". *) #i; ncases (H2 a p i); + (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-5". *) #x; *; #xC; #xP; + (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-5-1". *) @; + ##[ (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-6". *) napply x + ##| (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-7". *) + @; ##[ napply xC; + ##| (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-8". *) + napply (fish_rec ? U P); + (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-9". *) + nassumption; + ##] + ##] ##] nqed. - -notation "◃U" non associative with precedence 55 -for @{ 'coverage $U }. +(*DOCBEGIN +We introduce `i` and then we destruct `H2 a p i`, that being a proof +of an overlap predicate, give as an element and a proof that it is +both in `𝐂 a i` and `P`. +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-5] +We then introduce `x`, break the conjunction (the `*;` command is the +equivalent of `ncases` but operates on the first hypothesis that can +be introduced. We then introduce the two sides of the conjuction. +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-5-1] +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-6] +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-7] +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-8] +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-9] +DOCEND*) ndefinition coverage : ∀A:Ax.∀U:Ω^A.Ω^A ≝ λA,U.{ a | a ◃ U }. +notation "◃U" non associative with precedence 55 for @{ 'coverage $U }. + interpretation "coverage cover" 'coverage U = (coverage ? U). ndefinition cover_equation : ∀A:Ax.∀U,X:Ω^A.CProp[0] ≝ λA,U,X. @@ -430,7 +661,6 @@ naxiom setoidification : Bla Bla, -
foo
DOCEND*)