X-Git-Url: http://matita.cs.unibo.it/gitweb/?a=blobdiff_plain;f=helm%2Fsoftware%2Fmatita%2Fnlibrary%2Ftopology%2Figft.ma;h=66c7dd3a14e9dd9811d43847bb3aef37d7c0d829;hb=8d321a03cf328b85fe7c084bb22685673633d2ee;hp=3e9e359d5f01109f9743e7e0f0f7d27f1c303ee3;hpb=12bebae6f57b3a671a1aa29662d5ed7208a85667;p=helm.git diff --git a/helm/software/matita/nlibrary/topology/igft.ma b/helm/software/matita/nlibrary/topology/igft.ma index 3e9e359d5..66c7dd3a1 100644 --- a/helm/software/matita/nlibrary/topology/igft.ma +++ b/helm/software/matita/nlibrary/topology/igft.ma @@ -1,38 +1,414 @@ +(*DOCBEGIN + +Matita Tutorial: inductively generated formal topologies +======================================================== + +This is a not so short introduction to Matita, based on +the formalization of the paper + +> Between formal topology and game theory: an +> explicit solution for the conditions for an +> inductive generation of formal topologies + +by S.Berardi and S. Valentini. The tutorial is by Enrico Tassi. + +The tutorial spends a considerable amount of effort in defining +notations that resemble the ones used in the original paper. We believe +this a important part of every formalization, not only for the estetic +point of view, but also from the practical point of view. Being +consistent allows to follow the paper in a pedantic way, and hopefully +to make the formalization (at least the definitions and proved +statements) readable to the author of the paper. + +Orientering +----------- + +TODO + +buttons, PG-interaction-model, sequent window, script window, ncheck + +The library, inclusion of `sets/sets.ma`, notation defined: Ω^A. +Symbols (see menu: View ▹ TeX/UTF-8 Table): + +- ∀ `\Forall` +- λ `\lambda` +- ≝ `\def` +- → `->` + +Virtuals, ALT-L, for example `I` changes into `𝕀`, finally `𝐈`. + +The standard library and the `include` command +---------------------------------------------- + +Some basic notions, like subset, membership, intersection and union +are part of the standard library of Matita. + +These notions come with +some notation attached to them: + +- A ∪ B `A \cup B` +- A ∩ B `A \cap B` +- A ≬ B `A \between B` +- x ∈ A `x \in A` +- Ω^A, that is the type of the subsets of A, `\Omega ^ A` + +The `include` command tells Matita to load a part of the library, +in particular the part that we will use can be loaded as follows: + +DOCEND*) + include "sets/sets.ma". +(*HIDE*) +(* move away *) +nlemma subseteq_intersection_l: ∀A.∀U,V,W:Ω^A.U ⊆ W ∨ V ⊆ W → U ∩ V ⊆ W. +#A; #U; #V; #W; *; #H; #x; *; #xU; #xV; napply H; nassumption; +nqed. + +nlemma subseteq_union_l: ∀A.∀U,V,W:Ω^A.U ⊆ W → V ⊆ W → U ∪ V ⊆ W. +#A; #U; #V; #W; #H; #H1; #x; *; #Hx; ##[ napply H; ##| napply H1; ##] nassumption; +nqed. + +nlemma subseteq_intersection_r: ∀A.∀U,V,W:Ω^A.W ⊆ U → W ⊆ V → W ⊆ U ∩ V. +#A; #U; #V; #W; #H1; #H2; #x; #Hx; @; ##[ napply H1; ##| napply H2; ##] nassumption; +nqed. +(*UNHIDE*) + +(*DOCBEGIN + +Some basic results that we will use are also part of the sets library: + +- subseteq\_union\_l: ∀A.∀U,V,W:Ω^A.U ⊆ W → V ⊆ W → U ∪ V ⊆ W +- subseteq\_intersection\_r: ∀A.∀U,V,W:Ω^A.W ⊆ U → W ⊆ V → W ⊆ U ∩ V + +Defining Axiom set +------------------ + +records, projections, types of projections.. + +DOCEND*) + nrecord Ax : Type[1] ≝ { - S:> setoid; (* Type[0]; *) - I: S → Type[0]; - C: ∀a:S. I a → Ω ^ S + S :> setoid; + I : S → Type[0]; + C : ∀a:S. I a → Ω ^ S }. -notation "𝐈 \sub( ❨a❩ )" non associative with precedence 70 for @{ 'I $a }. -notation "𝐂 \sub ( ❨a,\emsp i❩ )" non associative with precedence 70 for @{ 'C $a $i }. +(*DOCBEGIN + +Note that the field `S` was declared with `:>` instead of a simple `:`. +This declares the `S` projection to be a coercion. A coercion is +a function case the system automatically inserts when it is needed. +In that case, the projection `S` has type `Ax → setoid`, and whenever +the expected type of a term is `setoid` while its type is `Ax`, the +system inserts the coercion around it, to make the whole term well types. + +When formalizing an algebraic structure, declaring the carrier as a +coercion is a common practice, since it allows to write statements like + + ∀G:Group.∀x:G.x * x^-1 = 1 + +The quantification over `x` of type `G` is illtyped, since `G` is a term +(of type `Group`) and thus not a type. Since the carrier projection +`carr` of `G` is a coercion, that maps a `Group` into the type of +its elements, the system automatically inserts `carr` around `G`, +obtaining `…∀x: carr G.…`. Coercions are also hidden by the system +when it displays a term. + +In this particular case, the coercion `S` allows to write + + ∀A:Ax.∀a:A.… + +Since `A` is not a type, but it can be turned into a `setoid` by `S` +and a `setoid` can be turned into a type by its `carr` projection, the +composed coercion `carr ∘ S` is silently inserted. + +Implicit arguments +------------------ + +Something that is not still satisfactory, in that the dependent type +of `I` and `C` are abstracted over the Axiom set. To obtain the +precise type of a term, you can use the `ncheck` command as follows. + +DOCEND*) + +(* ncheck I. *) +(* ncheck C. *) + +(*DOCBEGIN + +One would like to write `I a` and not `I A a` under a context where +`A` is an axiom set and `a` has type `S A` (or thanks to the coercion +mecanism simply `A`). In Matita, a question mark represents an implicit +argument, i.e. a missing piece of information the system is asked to +infer. Matita performs some sort of type inference, thus writing +`I ? a` is enough: since the second argument of `I` is typed by the +first one, the first one can be inferred just computing the type of `a`. + +DOCEND*) + +(* ncheck (∀A:Ax.∀a:A.I ? a). *) + +(*DOCBEGIN + +This is still not completely satisfactory, since you have always type +`?`; to fix this minor issue we have to introduce the notational +support built in Matita. + +Notation for I and C +-------------------- + +Matita is quipped with a quite complex notational support, +allowing the user to define and use mathematical notations +([From Notation to Semantics: There and Back Again][1]). + +Since notations are usually ambiguous (e.g. the frequent overloading of +symbols) Matita distinguishes between the term level, the +content level, and the presentation level, allowing multiple +mappings between the contenet and the term level. + +The mapping between the presentation level (i.e. what is typed on the +keyboard and what is displayed in the sequent window) and the content +level is defined with the `notation` command. When followed by +`>`, it defines an input (only) notation. + +DOCEND*) notation > "𝐈 term 90 a" non associative with precedence 70 for @{ 'I $a }. notation > "𝐂 term 90 a term 90 i" non associative with precedence 70 for @{ 'C $a $i }. +(*DOCBEGIN + +The forst notation defines the writing `𝐈 a` where `a` is a generic +term of precedence 90, the maximum one. This high precedence forces +parentheses around any term of a lower precedence. For example `𝐈 x` +would be accepted, since identifiers have precedence 90, but +`𝐈 f x` would be interpreted as `(𝐈 f) x`. In the latter case, parentheses +have to be put around `f x`, thus the accepted writing would be `𝐈 (f x)`. + +To obtain the `𝐈` is enough to type `I` and then cycle between its +similar symbols with ALT-L. The same for `𝐂`. Notations cannot use +regular letters or the round parentheses, thus their variants (like the +bold ones) have to be used. + +The first notation associates `𝐈 a` with `'I $a` where `'I` is a +new content element to which a term `$a` is passed. + +Content elements have to be interpreted, and possibly multiple, +incompatible, interpretations can be defined. + +DOCEND*) + interpretation "I" 'I a = (I ? a). interpretation "C" 'C a i = (C ? a i). -ndefinition cover_set ≝ λc:∀A:Ax.Ω^A → A → CProp[0].λA,C,U. - ∀y.y ∈ C → c A U y. +(*DOCBEGIN + +The `interpretation` command allows to define the mapping between +the content level and the terms level. Here we associate the `I` and +`C` projections of the Axiom set record, where the Axiom set is an implicit +argument `?` to be inferred by the system. + +Interpretation are bi-directional, thus when displaying a term like +`C _ a i`, the system looks for a presentation for the content element +`'C a i`. + +DOCEND*) + +notation < "𝐈 \sub( ❨a❩ )" non associative with precedence 70 for @{ 'I $a }. +notation < "𝐂 \sub( ❨a,\emsp i❩ )" non associative with precedence 70 for @{ 'C $a $i }. + +(*DOCBEGIN + +For output purposes we can define more complex notations, for example +we can put bold parenteses around the arguments of `𝐈` and `𝐂`, decreasing +the size of the arguments and lowering their baseline (i.e. putting them +as subscript), separating them with a comma followed by a little space. + +The first (technical) definition +-------------------------------- + +Before defining the cover relation as an inductive predicate, one +has to notice that the infinity rule uses, in its hypotheses, the +cover relation between two subsets, while the inductive predicate +we are going to define relates an element and a subset. + +An option would be to unfold the definition of cover between subsets, +but we prefer to define the abstract notion of cover between subsets +(so that we can attach a (ambiguous) notation to it). + +Anyway, to ease the understaing of the definition of the cover relation +between subsets, we first define the inductive predicate unfolding the +definition, and we later refine it with. + +DOCEND*) + +ninductive xcover (A : Ax) (U : Ω^A) : A → CProp[0] ≝ +| xcreflexivity : ∀a:A. a ∈ U → xcover A U a +| xcinfinity : ∀a:A.∀i:𝐈 a. (∀y.y ∈ 𝐂 a i → xcover A U y) → xcover A U a. + +(*DOCBEGIN + +We defined the xcover (x will be removed in the final version of the +definition) as an inductive predicate. The arity of the inductive +predicate has to be carefully analyzed: + +> (A : Ax) (U : Ω^A) : A → CProp[0] + +The syntax separates with `:` abstractions that are fixed for every +constructor (introduction rule) and abstractions that can change. In that +case the parameter `U` is abstracted once and forall in front of every +constructor, and every occurrence of the inductive predicate is applied to +`U` in a consistent way. Arguments abstracted on the right of `:` are not +constant, for example the xcinfinity constructor introduces `a ◃ U`, +but under the assumption that (for every y) `y ◃ U`. In that rule, the left +had side of the predicate changes, thus it has to be abstrated (in the arity +of the inductive predicate) on the right of `:`. + +DOCEND*) + +(* ncheck xcreflexivity. *) + +(*DOCBEGIN + +We want now to abstract out `(∀y.y ∈ 𝐂 a i → xcover A U y)` and define +a notion `cover_set` to which a notation `𝐂 a i ◃ U` can be attached. + +This notion has to be abstracted over the cover relation (whose +type is the arity of the inductive `xcover` predicate just defined). + +Then it has to be abstracted over the arguments of that cover relation, +i.e. the axiom set and the set U, and the subset (in that case `𝐂 a i`) +sitting on the left hand side of `◃`. + +DOCEND*) + +ndefinition cover_set : + ∀cover: ∀A:Ax.Ω^A → A → CProp[0]. ∀A:Ax.∀C,U:Ω^A. CProp[0] +≝ + λcover. λA, C,U. ∀y.y ∈ C → cover A U y. + +(*DOCBEGIN + +The `ndefinition` command takes a name, a type and body (of that type). +The type can be omitted, and in that case it is inferred by the system. +If the type is given, the system uses it to infer implicit arguments +of the body. In that case all types are left implicit in the body. + +We now define the notation `a ◃ b`. Here the keywork `hvbox` +and `break` tell the system how to wrap text when it does not +fit the screen (they can be safely ignore for the scope of +this tutorial). we also add an interpretation for that notation, +where the (abstracted) cover relation is implicit. The system +will not be able to infer it from the other arguments `C` and `U` +and will thus prompt the user for it. This is also why we named this +interpretation `covers set temp`: we will later define another +interpretation in which the cover relation is the one we are going to +define. + +DOCEND*) -(* a \ltri b *) notation "hvbox(a break ◃ b)" non associative with precedence 45 for @{ 'covers $a $b }. interpretation "covers set temp" 'covers C U = (cover_set ?? C U). +(*DOCBEGIN + +We can now define the cover relation using the `◃` notation for +the premise of infinity. + +DOCEND*) + ninductive cover (A : Ax) (U : Ω^A) : A → CProp[0] ≝ -| creflexivity : ∀a:A. a ∈ U → cover ? U a -| cinfinity : ∀a:A.∀i:𝐈 a. 𝐂 a i ◃ U → cover ? U a. +| creflexivity : ∀a. a ∈ U → cover ? U a +| cinfinity : ∀a. ∀i. 𝐂 a i ◃ U → cover ? U a. +(** screenshot "cover". *) napply cover; nqed. +(*DOCBEGIN + +Note that the system accepts the definition +but prompts the user for the relation the `cover_set` notion is +abstracted on. + +![The system asks for a cover relation][cover] + +The orizontal line separates the hypotheses from the conclusion. +The `napply cover` command tells the system that the relation +it is looking for is exactly our first context entry (i.e. the inductive +predicate we are defining, up to α-conversion); while the `nqed` command +ends a definition or proof. + +We can now define the interpretation for the cover relation between an +element and a subset fist, then between two subsets (but this time +we fixed the relation `cover_set` is abstracted on). + +DOCEND*) + interpretation "covers" 'covers a U = (cover ? U a). interpretation "covers set" 'covers a U = (cover_set cover ? a U). +(*DOCBEGIN + +We will proceed similarly for the fish relation, but before going +on it is better to give a short introduction to the proof mode of Matita. +We define again the `cover_set` term, but this time we will build +its body interactively. In λ-calculus Matita is based on, CIC, proofs +and terms share the same syntax, and it thus possible to use the +commands devoted to build proof term to build regular definitions. + +DOCEND*) + + +ndefinition xcover_set : + ∀c: ∀A:Ax.Ω^A → A → CProp[0]. ∀A:Ax.∀C,U:Ω^A. CProp[0]. +(** screenshot "xcover-set-1". *) +(*DOCBEGIN +The system asks for a proof of the full statement, in an empty context. +![xcover_set proof step ][xcover-set-1] +The `#` command in the ∀-introduction rule, it gives a name to an +assumption putting it in the context, and generates a λ-abstraction +in the proof term. +DOCEND*) +#cover; #A; #C; #U; (** screenshot "xcover-set-2". *) +(*DOCBEGIN +![xcover_set proof step ][xcover-set-2] +We have now to provide a proposition, and we exhibit it. We left +a part of it implicit; since the system cannot infer it it will +ask it later. Note that the type of `∀y:A.y ∈ C → ?` is a proposition +whenever `?` is. +DOCEND*) +napply (∀y:A.y ∈ C → ?); (** screenshot "xcover-set-3". *) +(*DOCBEGIN +![xcover_set proof step ][xcover-set-3] +The proposition we want to provide is an application of the +cover relation we have abstracted in the context. The command +`napply`, if the given term has not the expected type (in that +case it is a product versus a proposition) it applies it to as many +implicit arguments as necessary (in that case `? ? ?`). +DOCEND*) +napply cover; (** screenshot "xcover-set-4". *) +(*DOCBEGIN +![xcover_set proof step ][xcover-set-4] +The system will now ask in turn the three implicit arguments +passed to cover. The syntax `##[` allows to start a branching +to tackle every sub proof individually, otherwise every command +is applied to every subrpoof. The command `##|` switches to the next +subproof and `##]` ends the branching. +DOCEND*) +##[ napply A; +##| napply U; +##| napply y; +##] +nqed. + +(*DOCBEGIN +The definition of fish works exactly the same way as for cover, except +that it is defined as a coinductive proposition. +DOCEND*) + ndefinition fish_set ≝ λf:∀A:Ax.Ω^A → A → CProp[0]. λA,U,V. ∃a.a ∈ V ∧ f A U a. @@ -51,22 +427,96 @@ nqed. interpretation "fish set" 'fish A U = (fish_set fish ? U A). interpretation "fish" 'fish a U = (fish ? U a). +(*DOCBEGIN + +Matita is able to generate elimination rules for inductive types, +but not introduction rules for the coinductive case. + +DOCEND*) + +(* ncheck cover_rect_CProp0. *) + +(*DOCBEGIN + +We thus have to define the introduction rule for fish by corecursion. +Here we again use the proof mode of Matita to exhibit the body of the +corecursive function. + +DOCEND*) + nlet corec fish_rec (A:Ax) (U: Ω^A) (P: Ω^A) (H1: P ⊆ U) - (H2: ∀a:A. a ∈ P → ∀j: 𝐈 a. 𝐂 a j ≬ P): - ∀a:A. ∀p: a ∈ P. a ⋉ U ≝ ?. -#a; #p; napply cfish; -##[ napply H1; napply p; -##| #i; ncases (H2 a p i); #x; *; #xC; #xP; @; ##[napply x] - @; ##[ napply xC ] napply (fish_rec ? U P); nassumption; + (H2: ∀a:A. a ∈ P → ∀j: 𝐈 a. 𝐂 a j ≬ P): ∀a:A. ∀p: a ∈ P. a ⋉ U ≝ ?. +(** screenshot "def-fish-rec-1". *) +(*DOCBEGIN +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-1] +Note the first item of the context, it is the corecursive function we are +defining. This item allows to perform the recursive call, but we will be +allowed to do such call only after having generated a constructor of +the fish coinductive type. + +We introduce `a` and `p`, and then return the fish constructor `cfish`. +Since the constructor accepts two arguments, the system asks for them. +DOCEND*) +#a; #p; napply cfish; (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-2". *) +(*DOCBEGIN +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-2] +The first one is a proof that `a ∈ U`. This can be proved using `H1` and `p`. +With the `nchange` tactic we change `H1` into an equivalent form (this step +can be skipped, since the systeem would be able to unfold the definition +of inclusion by itself) +DOCEND*) +##[ nchange in H1 with (∀b.b∈P → b∈U); + + (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-2-1". *) napply H1; + (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-3". *) nassumption; +(*DOCBEGIN +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-2-1] +It is now clear that `H1` can be applied. Again `napply` adds two +implicit arguments to `H1 ? ?`, obtaining a proof of `? ∈ U` given a proof +that `? ∈ P`. Thanks to unification, the system understands that `?` is actually +`a`, and it asks a proof that `a ∈ P`. +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-3] +The `nassumption` tactic looks for the required proof in the context, and in +that cases finds it in the last context position. + +We move now to the second branch of the proof, corresponding to the second +argument of the `cfish` constructor. +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-4] +DOCEND*) +##| (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-4". *) #i; ncases (H2 a p i); + (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-5". *) #x; *; #xC; #xP; + (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-5-1". *) @; + ##[ (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-6". *) napply x + ##| (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-7". *) + @; ##[ napply xC; + ##| (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-8". *) + napply (fish_rec ? U P); + (** screenshot "def-fish-rec-9". *) + nassumption; + ##] + ##] ##] nqed. - -notation "◃U" non associative with precedence 55 -for @{ 'coverage $U }. +(*DOCBEGIN +We introduce `i` and then we destruct `H2 a p i`, that being a proof +of an overlap predicate, give as an element and a proof that it is +both in `𝐂 a i` and `P`. +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-5] +We then introduce `x`, break the conjunction (the `*;` command is the +equivalent of `ncases` but operates on the first hypothesis that can +be introduced. We then introduce the two sides of the conjuction. +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-5-1] +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-6] +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-7] +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-8] +![fish proof step][def-fish-rec-9] +DOCEND*) ndefinition coverage : ∀A:Ax.∀U:Ω^A.Ω^A ≝ λA,U.{ a | a ◃ U }. +notation "◃U" non associative with precedence 55 for @{ 'coverage $U }. + interpretation "coverage cover" 'coverage U = (coverage ? U). ndefinition cover_equation : ∀A:Ax.∀U,X:Ω^A.CProp[0] ≝ λA,U,X. @@ -122,6 +572,12 @@ nrecord nAx : Type[2] ≝ { nd: ∀a:nS. ∀i:nI a. nD a i → nS }. +(* +TYPE f A → B, g : B → A, f ∘ g = id, g ∘ g = id. + +a = b → I a = I b +*) + notation "𝐃 \sub ( ❨a,\emsp i❩ )" non associative with precedence 70 for @{ 'D $a $i }. notation "𝐝 \sub ( ❨a,\emsp i,\emsp j❩ )" non associative with precedence 70 for @{ 'd $a $i $j}. @@ -130,6 +586,7 @@ notation > "𝐝 term 90 a term 90 i term 90 j" non associative with precedence interpretation "D" 'D a i = (nD ? a i). interpretation "d" 'd a i j = (nd ? a i j). +interpretation "new I" 'I a = (nI ? a). ndefinition image ≝ λA:nAx.λa:A.λi. { x | ∃j:𝐃 a i. x = 𝐝 a i j }. @@ -154,15 +611,146 @@ ndefinition nAx_of_Ax : Ax → nAx. ##] nqed. -ninductive ord (A : nAx) : Type[0] ≝ - | oO : ord A - | oS : ord A → ord A - | oL : ∀a:A.∀i.∀f:𝐃 a i → ord A. ord A. +ninductive Ord (A : nAx) : Type[0] ≝ + | oO : Ord A + | oS : Ord A → Ord A + | oL : ∀a:A.∀i.∀f:𝐃 a i → Ord A. Ord A. + +notation "Λ term 90 f" non associative with precedence 50 for @{ 'oL $f }. +notation "x+1" non associative with precedence 50 for @{'oS $x }. -nlet rec famU (A : nAx) (U : Ω^A) (x : ord A) on x : Ω^A ≝ +interpretation "ordinals Lambda" 'oL f = (oL ? ? ? f). +interpretation "ordinals Succ" 'oS x = (oS ? x). + +nlet rec famU (A : nAx) (U : Ω^A) (x : Ord A) on x : Ω^A ≝ match x with [ oO ⇒ U - | oS y ⇒ let Un ≝ famU A U y in Un ∪ { x | ∃i.∀j:𝐃 x i.𝐝 x i j ∈ Un} + | oS y ⇒ let Un ≝ famU A U y in Un ∪ { x | ∃i.𝐈𝐦[𝐝 x i] ⊆ Un} | oL a i f ⇒ { x | ∃j.x ∈ famU A U (f j) } ]. -ndefinition ord_coverage ≝ λA,U.{ y | ∃x:ord A. y ∈ famU ? U x }. +notation < "term 90 U \sub (term 90 x)" non associative with precedence 50 for @{ 'famU $U $x }. +notation > "U ⎽ term 90 x" non associative with precedence 50 for @{ 'famU $U $x }. + +interpretation "famU" 'famU U x = (famU ? U x). + +ndefinition ord_coverage : ∀A:nAx.∀U:Ω^A.Ω^A ≝ λA,U.{ y | ∃x:Ord A. y ∈ famU ? U x }. + +ndefinition ord_cover_set ≝ λc:∀A:nAx.Ω^A → Ω^A.λA,C,U. + ∀y.y ∈ C → y ∈ c A U. + +interpretation "coverage new cover" 'coverage U = (ord_coverage ? U). +interpretation "new covers set" 'covers a U = (ord_cover_set ord_coverage ? a U). +interpretation "new covers" 'covers a U = (mem ? (ord_coverage ? U) a). + +ntheorem new_coverage_reflexive: + ∀A:nAx.∀U:Ω^A.∀a. a ∈ U → a ◃ U. +#A; #U; #a; #H; @ (oO A); napply H; +nqed. + +nlemma ord_subset: + ∀A:nAx.∀a:A.∀i,f,U.∀j:𝐃 a i.U⎽(f j) ⊆ U⎽(Λ f). +#A; #a; #i; #f; #U; #j; #b; #bUf; @ j; nassumption; +nqed. + +naxiom AC : ∀A,a,i,U.(∀j:𝐃 a i.∃x:Ord A.𝐝 a i j ∈ U⎽x) → (Σf.∀j:𝐃 a i.𝐝 a i j ∈ U⎽(f j)). + +naxiom setoidification : + ∀A:nAx.∀a,b:A.∀U.a=b → b ∈ U → a ∈ U. + +(*DOCBEGIN + +Bla Bla, + + +DOCEND*) + +alias symbol "covers" = "new covers". +alias symbol "covers" = "new covers set". +alias symbol "covers" = "new covers". +alias symbol "covers" = "new covers set". +alias symbol "covers" = "new covers". +alias symbol "covers" = "new covers set". +alias symbol "covers" = "new covers". +alias symbol "covers" = "new covers set". +alias symbol "covers" = "new covers". +ntheorem new_coverage_infinity: + ∀A:nAx.∀U:Ω^A.∀a:A. (∃i:𝐈 a. 𝐈𝐦[𝐝 a i] ◃ U) → a ◃ U. +#A; #U; #a;(** screenshot "figure1". *) +*; #i; #H; nnormalize in H; +ncut (∀y:𝐃 a i.∃x:Ord A.𝐝 a i y ∈ U⎽x); ##[ + #y; napply H; @ y; napply #; ##] #H'; +ncases (AC … H'); #f; #Hf; +ncut (∀j.𝐝 a i j ∈ U⎽(Λ f)); + ##[ #j; napply (ord_subset … f … (Hf j));##] #Hf'; +@ ((Λ f)+1); @2; nwhd; @i; #x; *; #d; #Hd; +napply (setoidification … Hd); napply Hf'; +nqed. + +nlemma new_coverage_min : + ∀A:nAx.∀U:qpowerclass A.∀V.U ⊆ V → (∀a:A.∀i.𝐈𝐦[𝐝 a i] ⊆ V → a ∈ V) → ◃(pc ? U) ⊆ V. +#A; #U; #V; #HUV; #Im; #b; *; #o; ngeneralize in match b; nchange with ((pc ? U)⎽o ⊆ V); +nelim o; +##[ #b; #bU0; napply HUV; napply bU0; +##| #p; #IH; napply subseteq_union_l; ##[ nassumption; ##] + #x; *; #i; #H; napply (Im ? i); napply (subseteq_trans … IH); napply H; +##| #a; #i; #f; #IH; #x; *; #d; napply IH; ##] +nqed. + +nlet rec famF (A: nAx) (F : Ω^A) (x : Ord A) on x : Ω^A ≝ + match x with + [ oO ⇒ F + | oS o ⇒ let Fo ≝ famF A F o in Fo ∩ { x | ∀i:𝐈 x.∃j:𝐃 x i.𝐝 x i j ∈ Fo } + | oL a i f ⇒ { x | ∀j:𝐃 a i.x ∈ famF A F (f j) } + ]. + +interpretation "famF" 'famU U x = (famF ? U x). + +ndefinition ord_fished : ∀A:nAx.∀F:Ω^A.Ω^A ≝ λA,F.{ y | ∀x:Ord A. y ∈ F⎽x }. + +interpretation "fished new fish" 'fished U = (ord_fished ? U). +interpretation "new fish" 'fish a U = (mem ? (ord_fished ? U) a). + +ntheorem new_fish_antirefl: + ∀A:nAx.∀F:Ω^A.∀a. a ⋉ F → a ∈ F. +#A; #F; #a; #H; nlapply (H (oO ?)); #aFo; napply aFo; +nqed. + +nlemma co_ord_subset: + ∀A:nAx.∀F:Ω^A.∀a,i.∀f:𝐃 a i → Ord A.∀j. F⎽(Λ f) ⊆ F⎽(f j). +#A; #F; #a; #i; #f; #j; #x; #H; napply H; +nqed. + +naxiom AC_dual : + ∀A:nAx.∀a:A.∀i,F. (∀f:𝐃 a i → Ord A.∃x:𝐃 a i.𝐝 a i x ∈ F⎽(f x)) → ∃j:𝐃 a i.∀x:Ord A.𝐝 a i j ∈ F⎽x. + + +ntheorem new_fish_compatible: + ∀A:nAx.∀F:Ω^A.∀a. a ⋉ F → ∀i:𝐈 a.∃j:𝐃 a i.𝐝 a i j ⋉ F. +#A; #F; #a; #aF; #i; nnormalize; +napply AC_dual; #f; +nlapply (aF (Λf+1)); #aLf; +nchange in aLf with (a ∈ F⎽(Λ f) ∧ ∀i:𝐈 a.∃j:𝐃 a i.𝐝 a i j ∈ F⎽(Λ f)); +ncut (∃j:𝐃 a i.𝐝 a i j ∈ F⎽(f j));##[ + ncases aLf; #_; #H; nlapply (H i); *; #j; #Hj; @j; napply Hj;##] #aLf'; +napply aLf'; +nqed. + +ntheorem max_new_fished: + ∀A:nAx.∀G,F:Ω^A.G ⊆ F → (∀a.a ∈ G → ∀i.𝐈𝐦[𝐝 a i] ≬ G) → G ⊆ ⋉F. +#A; #G; #F; #GF; #H; #b; #HbG; #o; ngeneralize in match HbG; ngeneralize in match b; +nchange with (G ⊆ F⎽o); +nelim o; +##[ napply GF; +##| #p; #IH; napply (subseteq_intersection_r … IH); + #x; #Hx; #i; ncases (H … Hx i); #c; *; *; #d; #Ed; #cG; + @d; napply IH; napply (setoidification … Ed^-1); napply cG; +##| #a; #i; #f; #Hf; nchange with (G ⊆ { y | ∀x. y ∈ F⎽(f x) }); + #b; #Hb; #d; napply (Hf d); napply Hb; +##] +nqed. + +(*DOCBEGIN + +[1]: http://upsilon.cc/~zack/research/publications/notation.pdf + +*) \ No newline at end of file