is not among the major achievements of the author (see e.g. \cite{Girard87}),
the result has been extensively investigated and there is a wide
literature on the
-topic (see e.g. \cite{Howard68,Troelstra,Girard87}.
+topic (see e.g. \cite{Troelstra,HS86,Girard87}, just to mention textbooks,
+and the bibliography therein).
A different, more neglected, but for many respects much more
direct relation between Peano (or Heyting) Arithmetics and
from the proof.
In spite of the simplicity and the elegance of the proof, it is extremely
difficult to find a modern discussion of this result; the most recent
-exposition we are aware of is in the encyclopedic (typewritten!) work by
-Troelstra \cite{Troelstra} (pp.213-229). Even modern introductory books
+exposition we are aware of is in the encyclopedic work by
+Troelstra \cite{Troelstra} (pp.213-229) going back to thirty years ago.
+Even modern introductory books
to Type Theory and Proof Theory devoting much space to system T
such as \cite{GLT} and \cite{TS} surprisingly leave out this simple and
-illuminating result. Both \cite{GLT} and \cite{TS}
+illuminating result. Both the previous textbooks
prefer to focus on higher order arithmetics and its relation with
Girard's System $F$ \cite{Girard86}, but the technical complexity and
the didactical value of the two proofs is not comparable: when you
des finiten Standpunktes. Dialectica, 12, pp.34-38, 1958.
\bibitem{Godel90}K.G\"odel. Collected Works. Vol.II, Oxford University Press,
1990.
+\bibitem{HS86}J.R.Hindley, J. P. Seldin. Introduction to Combinators and
+Lambda-calculus, Cambridge University Press, 1986.
\bibitem{Howard68}W.A.Howard. Functional interpretation of bar induction
by bar recursion. Compositio Mathematica 20, pp.107-124. 1958
\bibitem{Howard80}W.A.Howard. The formulae-as-types notion of constructions.